SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
vol.14 issue22EditorialThe natural vs. The human sciences:: myth, methodology and ontology author indexsubject indexarticles search
Home Pagealphabetic serial listing  

Services on Demand

Journal

Article

Indicators

Related links

  • On index processCited by Google
  • Have no similar articlesSimilars in SciELO
  • On index processSimilars in Google

Share


Discusiones Filosóficas

Print version ISSN 0124-6127

discus.filos vol.14 no.22 Manizales Jan./June 2013

 

Interpreting the wave function — what are electrons? And how do they move?

Interpretación de la función de onda—
¿qué son los electrones? Y ¿cómo se mueven?

Shan Gao
Institute for the History of Natural Sciences, Chinese Academy of Sciences, China.
gaoshan@ihns.ac.cn

Recibido el 18 de marzo de 2013 y aprobado el 13 de abril de 2013



Abstract

In quantum mechanics, the physical state of an electron is described by a wave function. According to the standard probability interpretation, the wave function of an electron is probability amplitude, and its modulus square gives the probability density of finding the electron in a certain position in space. In this article, we show that this central assumption of quantum mechanics may have an ontological extension. It is argued that microscopic particles such as electrons are indeed particles, but their motion is not continuous but discontinuous and random. On this view, the modulus square of the wave function not only gives the probability density of the particles being found in certain locations, but also gives the probability density of the particles being there. In other words, the wave function in quantum mechanics can be regarded as a representation of the state of random discontinuous motion of particles, and at a deeper level, it may represent the dispositional property of the particles that determines their random discontinuous motion.

Key words

electrons, dispositional property, probability density, random discontinuous motion, wave function.

Resumen

En la mecánica cuántica, el estado físico de un electrón es descrito por una función de onda. Según la interpretación de probabilidad estándar, la función de onda de un electrón es amplitud de probabilidad, y su modulo cuadrado da la densidad de probabilidad de encontrar el electrón en una cierta posición en el espacio. En este artículo, se muestra que esta suposición central de la mecánica cuántica puede tener una extensión ontológica. Se argumenta que las partículas microscópicas como los electrones son realmente partículas, pero su movimiento no es continuo, sino discontinuo y aleatorio. Desde esta perspectiva, el modulo cuadrado de la función de onda no sólo da la densidad de probabilidad de que las partículas se encuentren en ciertos lugares, sino que también da la densidad de probabilidad de que las partículas estén allí. En otras palabras, la función de onda en la mecánica cuántica se puede considerar como una representación del estado de movimiento discontinuo aleatorio de las partículas, y en un nivel más profundo, puede representar la propiedad disposicional de las partículas que determina su movimiento discontinuo aleatorio.

Palabras clave

electrones, propiedad disposicional, densidad de probabilidad, movimiento discontinuo aleatorio, función de onda.


The wave function gives not the density of stuff, but gives
rather (on squaring its modulus) the density of probability.
Probability of what, exactly? Not of the electron being there,
but of the electron being found there, if its position is
'measured'. Why this aversion to 'being' and insistence
on 'finding'? The founding fathers were unable to form a clear
picture of things on the remote atomic scale. (Bell)

Introduction

The physical meaning of the wave function is an important interpretative problem of quantum mechanics. The standard assumption is that the wave function of an electron is a probability amplitude, and its modulus square gives the probability density of finding the electron in a certain location at a given instant. This is usually called the probability interpretation of the wave function. Notwithstanding its great success, the probability interpretation is not wholly satisfactory because of resorting to the vague concept of measurement (Cf. Bell).

Recently a new penetrating analysis shows that the wave function not only gives the probability of getting different outcomes, but also may offer a faithful representation of reality (Pusey, Barrett and Rudolph). This analysis confirms the earlier result obtained based on protective measurements ((Aharonov and Vaidman) (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman, "Meaning of")), and shows that the standard probability interpretation of the wave function is ripe for rethinking. In fact, the realistic view of the wave function is already a common assumption in the main alternatives to quantum mechanics such as the de Broglie-Bohm theory and the many-worlds interpretation ((de Broglie) (Bohm) (Everett) (DeWitt and Graham)). Unfortunately, however, the precise meaning of the wave function is still an unresolved issue in these theories.

What, then, does the wave function truly represent? In this article, we will try to answer this fundamental question through a new analysis of protective measurements and the mass and charge distributions of a quantum system. The answer may help to understand the deep nature of quantum reality.

Measuring the state of a quantum system

The meaning of the wave function is often analyzed in the context of conventional (impulsive) measurements, for which the coupling interaction between the measured system and the measuring device is of short duration and strong. As a result, even though the wave function of a quantum system is in general extended over space, an ideal position measurement can only detect the system in a random position in space1. Then it is unsurprising that the wave function is assumed to be related to the probability of the random measurement result by the standard probability interpretation. This also indicates that conventional measurements cannot obtain enough information about a single quantum system to determine what physical state its wave function represents.

Fortunately, it has been known that the physical state of a single quantum system can be protectively measured ((Aharonov and Vaidman) (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman "Meaning of") (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman, "The meaning of") (Vaidman))2. A general method is to let the measured system be in a nondegenerate eigenstate of the whole Hamiltonian using a suitable protective interaction (in some situations the protection is provided by the measured system itself), and then make the measurement adiabatically so that the state of the system neither collapses nor becomes entangled with the measuring device appreciably. In general, the measured state needs to be known beforehand in order to arrange a proper protection. In this way, such protective measurements can measure the expectation values of observables on a single quantum system, and in particular, the mass and charge distributions of a quantum system as one part of its physical state, as well as its wave function, can be measured as expectation values of certain observables. Since the principle of protective measurement is independent of the controversial collapse postulate and only based on the linear Schrödinger evolution (for microscopic systems such as electrons) and the Born rule3, which are two established parts of quantum mechanics, its result as predicted by quantum mechanics can be used to investigate the meaning of the wave function4.

According to protective measurement, the charge of a charged quantum system such as an electron is distributed throughout space, and the charge density in each position is proportional to the modulus square of the wave function of the system there. Historically, the charge density interpretation for electrons was originally suggested by Schrödinger when he introduced the wave function and founded wave mechanics (Schrödinger). Schrödinger clearly realized that the charge density cannot be classical because his equation does not include the usual classical interaction between the densities. Presumably since people thought that the charge density could not be measured and also lacked a consistent physical picture, this initial interpretation of the wave function was soon rejected and replaced by Born's probability interpretation (Born). Now protective measurement re-endows the charge distribution of an electron with reality by a more convincing argument. The question then is how to find a consistent physical explanation for it5. Our following analysis can be regarded as a further development of Schrödinger's original idea to some extent. The twist is: that the charge distribution is not classical does not imply its non-existence; rather, its existence may point to a new, non-classical picture of quantum reality that hides behind the mathematical wave function.

Electrons are particles

The key to unveil the meaning of the wave function is to find the physical origin of the charge distribution. The charge distribution of a quantum system such as an electron has two possible existent forms: It is either real or effective. The distribution is real means that it exists throughout space at the same time, e.g. there are different charges in different positions at any instant. The distribution is effective means that there is only a localized particle with the total charge of the system in one position at every instant, and the time average of its motion (during an infinitesimal time interval) forms the effective distribution in the whole space. Moreover, since the integral of the formed charge density in any region is required to be equal to the average value of the total charge in the region, the motion of the particle is ergodic.

These two existent forms of the charge distribution of a quantum system have different physical effects, and thus they can be distinguished. Experiments show that different charges in different positions at a given instant have electrostatic interaction, while a charge at one instant has no electrostatic interaction with the charge at another instant. Therefore, if the charge distribution is effective, then there will exist no electrostatic self-interaction of the distribution, while if the charge distribution is real, then there will exist electrostatic self-interaction of the distribution. In short, the first form entails the existence of electrostatic self-interaction of the charge distribution of a quantum system, while the second form does not.

Since the existence of electrostatic self-interaction is inconsistent with the superposition principle of quantum mechanics, and especially, the existence of such electrostatic self-interaction for individual electrons already contradicts experimental observations (e.g. the results of the double-slit experiments with single electrons)6, the charge distribution of a quantum system such as an electron must be effective. This means that at every instant there is only a localized particle with the total mass and charge of the system, and during an infinitesimal time interval the time average of the ergodic motion of the particle forms the effective mass and charge distributions of the system. In short, electrons are particles, and their charge distributions in space, which are measureable by protective measurements, are formed by the ergodic motion of these particles.

Particles move in a discontinuous and random way

The next question is which sort of ergodic motion the particles undergo. If the ergodic motion of a particle is continuous, then it can only form the mass and charge distributions during a finite time interval. But the mass and charge distributions of a quantum system at each instant, which is proportional to the modulus square of the wave function of the system at the instant, is required to be formed during an infinitesimal time interval near the instant. Thus it seems that the ergodic motion of the particle cannot be continuous.

We can also reach this conclusion by analyzing a concrete example. Consider an electron in a superposition of two energy eigenstates in two separated boxes Y1(x) + Y2(x). In this example, even if one assumes that the electron as a localized particle can move with infinite velocity, it cannot continuously move from one box to another due to the restriction of box walls. Therefore, any sort of continuous motion cannot generate the effective charge density e|Y1(x) + Y2(x)|2. One may object that this is merely an artifact of the idealization of infinite potential. However, even in this ideal situation, the model should also be able to generate the effective charge distribution by means of some sort of ergodic motion of the electron; otherwise it will be inconsistent with quantum mechanics7.

On the other hand, if the motion of a particle is discontinuous, then the particle can readily move throughout all regions where the wave function is nonzero during an arbitrarily short time interval at a given instant. Furthermore, if the probability density of the particle appearing in each position is proportional to the modulus square of its wave function there at every instant, the discontinuous motion can also generate the right effective mass and charge distributions. This may solve the problems plagued by the classical ergodic models. The discontinuous ergodic motion requires no existence of a finite ergodic time. A particle undergoing discontinuous motion can also move from one region to another spatially separated region, no matter whether there is an infinite potential wall between them, and such discontinuous motion is not influenced by the environment and setup between these regions either.

In conclusion, we have argued that the mass and charge distributions of a quantum system such as an electron are formed by the discontinuous motion of a localized particle with the total mass and charge of the system, and the probability density of the particle appearing in each position is proportional to the modulus square of its wave function there.

Meaning of the wave function

According to the above analysis, microscopic particles such as electrons are indeed particles. Here the concept of particle is used in its usual sense. A particle is a small localized object with mass and charge, and it is only in one position in space at an instant. Moreover, the motion of these particles is not continuous but discontinuous in nature. We may say that an electron is a quantum particle in the sense that its motion is not continuous motion described by classical mechanics, but discontinuous motion described by quantum mechanics.

From a logical point of view, for the discontinuous motion of a quantum particle, there should exist a probabilistic instantaneous condition that determines the probability density of the particle appearing in every position in space, otherwise it would not "know" how frequently they should appear in each position in space. In other words, the particle should have an instantaneous property that determines its motion in a probabilistic way. This property is usually called indeterministic disposition or propensity in the literature8. As a result, the position of the particle at every instant is random, and its trajectory formed by the random position series is also discontinuous. In short, the motion of the particle is essentially discontinuous and random.

Unlike the deterministic continuous motion, the trajectory function x(t) can no longer provide a useful description for random discontinuous motion. For a quantum particle, there is no continuous trajectory at all. Rather, the random discontinuous motion of the particle forms a particle "cloud" extending throughout space (in an infinitesimal time interval), and the state of motion of the particle is represented by the density and flux density of the cloud, denoted by p(x, t) and j(x, t), respectively. This is similar to the description of a classical fluid in hydrodynamics. But their physical meanings are different. The particle cloud is formed by the random discontinuous motion of a single particle, and the density of the cloud, p(x, t), represents the objective probability density of the particle appearing in position x at instant t. By assuming that the nonrelativistic equation of motion is the Schrödinger equation in quantum mechanics9, the complex wave function Y(x, t) can be uniquely expressed by p(x, t) and j(x, t) (except for a constant phase factor):

In this way, the wave function Y(x, t) also provides a complete description of the state of random discontinuous motion of a particle.

The description of the motion of a single particle can be extended to the motion of many particles. At each instant the quantum system of N particles can be represented by a point in a 3N-dimensional configuration space, and the motion of these particles forms a cloud in the configuration space. Then, similar to the single particle case, the state of the system is represented by the density and flux density of the cloud in the configuration space, p(x1, x2…, xN) and j(x1, x2…, xN), where the density p(x1, x2…, xN) represents the probability density of particle 1 appearing in position x1 and particle 2 appearing in position x2, …, and particle N appearing in position xN. Since these two quantities are defined not in the real three-dimensional space, but in the 3N-dimensional configuration space, the many-particle wave function, which is composed of these two quantities, is also defined in the 3N-dimensional configuration space.

One important point needs to be stressed here. Since the wave function in quantum mechanics is defined at a given instant, not during an infinitesimal time interval, it should be regarded not simply as a description of the state of motion of particles, but more suitably as a description of the dispositional property of the particles that determines their random discontinuous motion at a deeper level10. In particular, the modulus square of the wave function determines the probability density of the particles appearing in certain positions in space. By contrast, the density and flux density of the particle cloud, which are defined during an infinitesimal time interval at a given instant, are only a description of the state of the resulting random discontinuous motion of particles, and they are determined by the wave function. In this sense, we may say that the motion of particles is "guided" by their wave function in a probabilistic way.

Conclusions

In this article, we have argued that quantum mechanics may have already spelled out the meaning of the wave function. There are three main steps to reach this conclusion.

First of all, protective measurement, whose principle is based on the established parts of quantum mechanics, shows that the charge of a charged quantum system such as an electron is distributed throughout space, and the charge density in each position is proportional to the modulus square of its wave function there. Next, the superposition principle of quantum mechanics requires that the charge distribution is effective, that is, it is formed by the ergodic motion of a localized particle with the total charge of the system. Lastly, the consistency of the formed distribution with that predicted by quantum mechanics requires that the ergodic motion of the particle is discontinuous, and the probability density of the particle appearing in every position is equal to the modulus square of its wave function there.

Therefore, quantum mechanics seems to imply that the wave function describes the state of random discontinuous motion of particles, and at a deeper level, it represents the dispositional property of the particles that determines their random discontinuous motion. In particular, the modulus square of the wave function not only gives the probability density of the particles being found in certain locations as the standard probability interpretation assumes, but also gives the probability density of the particles being there. It will be interesting to see how this new interpretation of the wave function can be extended to quantum field theory and what it implies for the solutions to the measurement problem.


Footnotes

1 In this article we only consider the spatial wave functions of quantum systems.
2 Note that the earlier objections to the validity and meaning of protective measurements have been answered ((Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman, "The meaning of") (Dass and Qureshi) (Vaidman) (Gao, "Comment on")).
3 It is worth noting that the possible existence of very slow collapse of the wave function for microscopic systems does not influence the principle of protective measurement.
4 It can be expected that protective measurements will be realized in the near future with the rapid development of quantum technologies (Cf. Lundeen et al.).
5 The proponents of protective measurement did not analyze the origin of the charge distribution. According to them, this type of measurement implies that the wave function of a single quantum system is a real physical wave (Aharonov, Anandan and Vaidman, "Meaning of").
6 As another example, consider the electron in the hydrogen atom. If there exists such electrostatic self-interaction for individual electrons, then since the potential of the electrostatic self-interaction is of the same order as the Coulomb potential produced by the nucleus, the energy levels of hydrogen atoms will be remarkably different from those predicted by quantum mechanics and confirmed by experiments. For a detailed analysis see Gao ("The wave function", "Meaning of the", "Interpreting quantum").
7 It is very common in quantum optics experiments that a single-photon wave packet is split into two branches moving along two well separated paths in space. In particular, the experimental results are not influenced by the environment and setup between the two paths of the photon. Thus it is very difficult to imagine that the photon performs a continuous ergodic motion back and forth in the space between its two paths.
8 It is worth stressing that the propensities possessed by the particles relate to their objective motion, not to the measurements on them as in the existing propensity interpretations of quantum mechanics (Cf. Suarez).
9 For a derivation of the free Schrödinger equation see Gao ("Interpreting quantum").
10 For a many-particle system in an entangled state, this dispositional property is possessed by the whole system.


References bibliographical

Aharonov, Y., Anandan, J. and L. Vaidman. "Meaning of the wave function". Phys. Rev. 1993: 4616. Print.         [ Links ]

---. "The meaning of protective measurements" Found. Phys. 1996: 117. Print.         [ Links ]

Aharonov, Y. and L. Vaidman. "Measurement of the Schrödinger wave of a single particle". Phys. Lett. 1993: 178-238. Print.         [ Links ]

Bell, J. S. "Against 'measurement'". Miller, A. I. (ed.). Sixty-Two years of uncertainty: Historical philosophical and physics enquiries into the foundations of quantum mechanics. Berlin: Springer, 1990. Print.         [ Links ]

Bohm, D. "A suggested interpretation of quantum theory in terms of "hidden" variables, I and II". Phys. Rev. Jan. 1952: 166-193. Print.         [ Links ]

Born, M. "Quantenmechanik der Stovorgänge". Z. Phys. 1926: 803-827. Print.         [ Links ]

Dass, N. D. H. and T. Qureshi. "Critique of protective measurements". Phys. Rev. 1999: 2590. Print.         [ Links ]

DeWitt, B. S. and N. Graham (eds.). The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973. Print.         [ Links ]

Everett, H. "'Relative state' formulation of quantum mechanics". Rev. Mod. Phys. Jun. 1957: 454-462. Print.         [ Links ]

Gao, S. "Comment on "How to protect the interpretation of the wave function against protective measurements" by Jos Uffink". Phil. Sci. Dec. 2011. Online.         [ Links ]

---. "The wave function and quantum reality". Khrennikov, A., Jaeger, G., Schlosshauer, M. and G. Weihs (eds.). Proceedings of the International Conference on Advances in Quantum Theory. Boston: American Institute of Physics, 2011. Print.         [ Links ]

---. "Meaning of the wave function". International Journal of Quantum Chemistry. Dec. 2011: 4124-4138. Print.         [ Links ]

---. "Interpreting quantum mechanics in terms of random discontinuous motion of particles". Phil. Sci. Feb. 2013. Online.         [ Links ]

Lundeen, J. S. et al. "Direct measurement of the quantum wave function". Physical Review Letters. Feb. 2012: 188-191. Print.         [ Links ]

Pusey, M., Barrett, J. and T. Rudolph. "On the reality of the quantum state". Nature Phys. 2012: 475-478. Online.         [ Links ]

Schrödinger, E. "Quantizierung als Eigenwertproblem (Vierte Mitteilung)". Ann. d. Phys. 1926: 109-139. Online.         [ Links ]

Suarez, M. "Quantum propensities". Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. Jun. 2007: 418-438. Online.         [ Links ]

Vaidman, L. "Protective measurements". Greenberger, D., Hentschel, K. and F. Weinert (eds.). Compendium of Quantum Physics: Concepts, Experiments, History and Philosophy. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2009. Print.         [ Links ]